The fidelity thesis is where Solum ties his account of
orginalism to substantive issues of law. There are two general lines of questions concerning
the fidelity thesis. One line concerns
the relationship between the fidelity thesis and the rest of Semantic
Originalism, while the other concerns the substance and import of the fidelity
thesis itself. The fidelity thesis “maintains
that because the semantic content of the Constitution is the supreme law of the
land, we are obligated by it, unless there is an overriding reason of morality
to the contrary.”
The fidelity thesis is not just a general claim that judges
have some obligation of fidelity to law (or, more broadly, that citizens or
officials, etc. have such a duty). Solum
has a stronger thesis in mind, some of which is not really argued for in this
particular essay. The semantic content
is the supreme law of the land, for example, is not a consequence of the other
three theses. This is a gap in the
explication of the contribution thesis, at least. The Constitution says it is the supreme law
of the land, and the Constitution is the conventional public meaning of the
document when adopted, but the fidelity thesis does not follow from those
claims. What we are committed to thus
far is the view that the semantic content of the Constitution directly
contributes to (or is part of) the law. That
does not say that we need overriding moral reasons to set aside the semantic
content, or that the semantic content dominates other sources of law, etc. What is says is that the semantic content is
one source we must consider in explicating U.S. law. To repeat from an earlier post, practice and
decisions, etc., are not allocated any particular roles by any of the three
theses before the fidelity thesis. As a
result, the fidelity thesis does not follow directly from the other three
theses, and there must be substantive normative argument for the fidelity
thesis. There is no plausible sense in
which the fidelity thesis can be read as a claim of fact. There really isn’t any argument for it in this
essay. It may be defensible and may even
be right, but in the context of this essay, it rests as an assumption only.
To be sure, Solum does offer a survey of arguments in favor
of fidelity to law, understood as an obligation to obey the law. But fidelity to law is not the fidelity thesis. The thesis is quite different – it demands
fidelity to original conventional public meaning and permits deviation only for
overriding moral reasons. The arguments
for fidelity to law are not arguments for the fidelity thesis. They are arguments for an obligation to obey
or comply with law, and they have no genuine connection to Semantic
Orginialism. That is to say, the arguments
for fidelity to law proceed on the basis of a general account of law and
general assumptions about the state of the law.
They are arguments about obligations within a reasonably just state, not
arguments about why those within the jurisdiction of the United States are
obligated to obey the laws of the United States, they are not arguments about
why one ought to obey the Constitution understood as original public meaning. Hence fidelity to law tells us nothing about
whether the Supreme Court are under an obligation to render decisions which “comply
with and [are] grounded on the semantic content of the Constitution.” That is a non sequitur, unless one adopts Solum’s
particular fidelity thesis; but that thesis is not defended in the essay.
“Fidelity to law by Supreme Court Justices would require
that their constitutional decisions both comply with and be grounded on the semantic
content of the Constitution. Decisions
that are inconsistent with the semantic content [of the Constitution] should be
considered “out of bounds” and opinions that do not respect the legal force of
the original meaning are illegitimate. These
conclusions are qualified, however. One
source of qualification is the doctrine of precedent or stare decisis. A second qualification is introduced by the
possibility of constitutional evil: semantic
content that would trigger the overriding reasons proviso that is a component
of the ideal of fidelity to law.” (158).
This is a troubling paragraph. The conclusions set out just do not follow
from the preceding three theses. They
are considerably stronger than what can be drawn from the three theses and
including the notion of fidelity to law. More directly, the presentation is not even
fully in accord with what has been committed to. The conclusions should not be set out as they
are – it is not that Solum has given reasons for these conclusions, which we
might then modify or qualify in some ways. He just can’t get that far. The “qualifications”, for all the argument to
date, may swallow the semantic content. Secondly, nothing at all about fidelity to law
even suggests that departures from semantic content are “out of bounds”
presumptively, defesably, or in any other way.
Finally, we have nothing yet to tell us what “the legal force of the original
meaning” is. It is therefore difficult
to make out the sense of failing to respect the legal force. As the import of the paragraph is to strip
certain Supreme Court decisions of legal force, to hold them illegitimate, one
can and should ask for more.
Recent Comments