What are the sources of obligation under a legal system? Put the question in another way starting from Solum’s Formalism, or, more accurately, from a relatively recent post on the subject in which he argues that we should reject the following proposition (he calls Constitutional Exclusivism):
It is the constitution (and not judicial decisions) that is a genuine source of normative authority. We are obligated by the Constitution and not by precedent.
Solum rejects the proposition and argues that we ought to accept supplemental sources for normative authority (of law). Solum uses this as a starting point for a series of arguments leading to conclusions about the propriety of stare decisis, i.e., binding precedential authority concerning interpretation of law. (I know that is a slightly odd way to express it, but bear with me.) I do want to discuss Solum’s argument, but there is an important diversion to be taken before that topic is reached: “We are obligated by the Constitution and not by precedent.” An interpretation of the proposition (not Solum’s): the source of legal obligation in the U.S is the Constitution, not precedent (of judicial or executive agencies). Can a formalist believe that? Yes. The proposition is not about the sources for understanding the extent of the demands of law. It is not even about the sources of law. It is about the source for an obligation to obey (the law). A Constitutional Exclusivist in this sense is adhering to a family of political theories, not particularly a family of interpretative theories. Originalism is sort of beside the point here.
What difference would this thesis make? Well, it constrains the account one gives of legitimate state action, or the limits of legal authority. Assume for the moment the Constitution is to be seen as a compact. (I have a suspicion that originalists are stuck with a compact theory. I am not an originalist, and it is not straightforward to connect theories of interpretation of law with political theories. As I recall, e.g., Vashukanis [] had a fairly conservative textualist approach. (It has been al long while since I read that work so may be making it all up.)) A Constitutionalist Exclusivist seems to me to committed to understanding the compact of the Constitution as strongly regulative; the authority of government within the Union lies with and derives from the Constitution, no action outside the boundaries set by the Constitution carries a genuine claim to authority (or obligation, if you prefer). One has an obligation as a citizen to the Constitution (and the arrangements consequent to it) rather than to the state. One can then generate an explanation for the distribution of powers within the governmental framework, including allocation of derivative authority to a judiciary. Having done that, one returns to the topic Solum is addressing, which concerns the interpretative theory. One more side trip before catching up with Prof. Solum, however. I do not think that either Constitutional Exclusivism or a strongly regulative compact entail acceptance of originalism. (Formalist may, but that is for another discussion.) One can be committed to the Constitution as the fundamental source of authority and believe that the participants in the drafting have no special precedence in understanding beyond the most general levels of abstraction. Similarly, a strongly regulative compact view entails commitments concerning the nature of the legitimacy of state action and views about the relationships between state and populations within the effective power of the state. But the compact need not be seen as just a lease agreement writ large. Given that most people will be inclined to link the compact to moral legitimacy, to adoption or acceptance of political and moral principles, historically fixed accounts of the contours of the compact would take on an additional persuasive burden. To put simply, it is compact, not a revelation.
So now, Solum is at the point of arguing that the Supreme Court ought to be bound by its own precedents and that such a commitment is the best expression of formalist (and originalist?) theory accepting the modified exclusivist position.
Solum argues then that formalism is a good road “back” to originalism, and that it counsels that precedent bind by the consistency with which the earlier court decision’s reasoning is a good faith effort to adhere to originalism with respect to Constitution (and legislation). Could well be. I don’t think originalism is very good goal, but set that to the side. Does formalism inevitably lead us to originalism? Takes more thought than I have yet given it to decide that question, but I am happy to offer some preliminary suggestions on the topic. I think the piece that may turn out to be central is Solum’s ordering of the interpretive rules of his formulation of formalism. As he puts it:
Principle One, Precedent: Judges in constitutional cases should follow an adequate and articulated doctrine of stare decisis. Among the features of such a doctrine is that even courts of last resort (i.e. the United States Supreme Court) should regard their own decisions as binding, unless there is a compelling reason to do otherwise.
Principle Two, Plain Meaning: When the precedents run out, judges should look to the plain meaning of the salient provisions of the constitutional text.
Principle Three, Intratextualism and Structure: When the text of a particular provision(s) is ambiguous, judges should construe that provision so as to be consistent with other related provisions and with the the structure of the Constitution as a whole.
Principle Four, Original Meaning: If ambiguity still persists, judges should make a good faith effort to determine the original meaning, where original meaning is understood to be the meaning that (i) the framers would have reasonably expected (ii) the audience to whom the Constitution is addressed (ratifiers, contemporary interpreters), (iii) to attribute to the framers, (iv) based on the evidence (public record) that was publicly available. (Adapting Grice's formulation of speaker's meaning.)
Principle Five, Default Rules: And when ambiguity persists after all of that, then judges should resort to general default rules that minimize their own discretion and maximize the predictability and certainty of the law. (And in this post, I will only offer a promissory note with repsect to the content of such principles.)
Principle Six, Lexicality and Holism The first five principles are to be understood as lexically ordered in the following sense. Judges should order their deliberations by the first five principles--attempting to structure their conscious deliberations by attending to the features highlighted by each each principle in order before proceeding to the next principle. But this requirement does not entail that judges either will not or should not recognize that the considerations thematized by one principle may be relevant to deliberations explicitly organized by another principle. Thus, the interpretation of a precedent will sometimes (perhaps always) require consideration of the text, structure, and original meaning, and so forth. (Lexical ordering is a guideline for structuring deliberation, and is not inconsistent with the observation that interpretation involves what Gadamer called the hermeneutic circle.) These are principles not rules, and lexical ordering operates a methodological heuristic and not as a rigid rule.
Because they are lexically ordered, it is a real question whether anything will ever remain for Principle 4 to determine. I think it would be rather rarer than an originalist could tolerate. But that does tell us whether the Principle is inevitably there. In one sense, absolutely must be because it is Larry’s theory and he says it is part of the theory. In another sense, I think the issue is whether speaker’s meanings is what we should or do care about, even in the instances when there is something for Principle 4 to address. I think not, but I can’t yet tell if any of my reasons for that answer are reasons someone like Solum should care about.
Recent Comments