Heidi Hurd published an interesting book on civil disobedinece (Moral Combat). In between the torments of discovery in a case that raises genuine Rule 11 issues (one of the things which happens when judges get to know attorneys is that the judges ignore the rules and let the good buddy litigate things in the belief that somewhere down the road something will turn up to make the case something more than risible, even if far from enough to get to trial) and drafting the inevitable motion for summary judgment, I have been reading Prof. Hurd’s book. Today starts a series recording some thoughts in reaction to that work.
Hurd’s view seem to me to arise from basic commitments about the nature of morality and moral epistemology. Reconstructed, I understand her argument, in the first instance, to be this:
Rightness of conduct is not tied to or dependent on epistemological claims. That an action is right has no useful implications for the question of knowledge (or even reasonable belief?) that it is right. This claim follows from her view that the rightness of an action is objective and not epistemic. In the context of law, this in turn entails distinguishing between, on the one hand, culpable and non-culpable conduct, and, on the other hand, between justified and unjustified conduct. Determinations of culpability turn on epistemic evaluations. Culpable action is action the actor believes to be wrong or which the actor unjustifiably believes is right. (The ‘unjustifiably believes’ is Hurd’s phrasing. I would have expected the standard to be ‘unreasonably believes.’ It could be that justification here necessarily incorporates a reasonableness standard; I need to check that.) In any event, the line between culpable and non-culpable is based on assessment of the intent and epistemic state of the actor. Culpability is a normal condition for punishment. Justified and unjustified are derived from consideration of the relationship of the action and actor to rightness. As I understand it, an action is unjustified if it is not right, and, conversely, an action is justified by rightness. Rightness, for Hurd, is a function of the degree the action satisfies objective criteria specified by the best normative theory. Right actions are justified. The justifiability of an action determines the justifiability of preventing such conduct.
So, to put a little clothing on the apparatus, an action may be prevented to the extent that it is unjustified. The state may prevent actions through punishment (presumably as one among a variety of methods, although Hurd skips over that in this book). A justified action therefore is one that should not be punished. It is also true under this approach that an unjustified action need not be punishable, because it may not be culpable. For example, if the action is unjustified but the actor is non-culpable because the actor justifiably believed the conduct was right (or justified). There are then two modalities for normative assessment: the objective standards of justifiability and the epistemic standards of culpability. Presumably the latter are characterized as a kind of social convention regarding beliefs, a floating world of conventions and conventional (or maybe intersubjective) agreements about reasoning and beliefs. The former should be something else, but I am unsure how that is to be.
The ‘objective’ standard is characterized as ‘degree the action satisfies objective criteria specified by the best normative theory’. So the criteria (indicating degree of satisfaction) are objective, but the theory for which they are criteria is not (‘best normative theory’ can’t be an interestingly objective category – the point of that description has to be to forestall questions of truth regarding the normative theory). I would expect that ‘objective’ here is intended to require that the criteria be things about the world which are either, in an uncritical sense, true (questions of fact would be a way to say it) or about which there is no real possibility of sane dissent. I am not sure that I have a good sense of what would count as objective criteria. I have a good enough sense of what would count as reasonable reasoning processes and reasonable beliefs about factual questions, i.e., beliefs about the state of the world and how the world works, but I would be disinclined to talk about that as objective criteria of much of anything, unless ‘objective’ is emptied of ordinary meaning. One example would do it: what to do about people who talk to God? Maybe the Pope does. Certainly the President of the LDS Church talks with God. Having conversations with God would seem like a good source of information, God being the creator and animator of it all. On the other hand, it is hard to take talking to God seriously. I don’t know how any of this gets handled on objective criteria. But this kind of worry can be resolved, I think, with a moderate amount of work and some good faith engagement. Doing that highlights what I think (for now, anyway) is a more fundamental problem, which is that it seems difficult to specify what would count as objective criteria until after the ‘best normative theory’ is identified.
I have to return to the unhappy in purgatory – the associates struggling with msj.
Recent Comments